THE CONCEPTS OF TRUTH AND LAW IN MEDICINE


Scientific investigation consists in questioning nature in accordance with the hypothesis of this constant interphenomenal relationship. The object of the scientific intellect is always the same: to create for the human intelligence as faithful and serviceable a representation of the conditions under which phenomena appear as may be possible.


“There is something harder and stronger than bronze or marble: It is a prejudice.” – HORACE.

“The search for truth is the supreme goal toward which science struggles. We pursue truth and yet, when almost perceived, it frightens us. Deceiving us time and again, this phantom appears for an instant, and is gone; we must pursue it further and ever further, without hope of overtaking it and he who would joint in this pursuit of truth must bee absolutely independent, he must completely free his soul of prejudices and passions; he must resolve himself to an absolute sincerity.” 1. Introduction of the Thesis made by the author of the Law of Similars.

“It would seem almost impossible to find at the present time an unprejudiced observer. All men are prejudiced. Man is fixed in his politics, fixed in his religion, fixed in his ideas of medicine; because of his prejudice he cannot reason. You need only talk to him a moment on these subjects and he will begin to tell you what he thinks, he will give his opinion, as if that had anything to do with it.”2 (Kents Lecture of Homoeopathic Philosophy, Lecture II).

“An unprejudiced student is the only true scientific observer, And it is only to the extent to which we can really free ourselves from preconceived ideas that scientific truth united with moral truth can procure joy for us. These verities entice us and elude us; even in the moment when the pursuing mortal believes himself to have attained to her feet, truth is gone, and he is condemned ever to follow after, nor may he know repose.”3 (3 H. Poincare. La valeur de la Science).

Science.

According to Boutroux, science is: “The hypothesis of a constant relation between phenomena and an indefinitely perfectible induction.” Science no longer dreams of giving the intellect an image of externalities which perhaps do not exist; it exposes relationships that may be obviously verified by experience. And this is sufficient to justify our applying to science the adjective true.

Scientific investigation consists in questioning nature in accordance with the hypothesis of this constant interphenomenal relationship. The object of the scientific intellect is always the same: to create for the human intelligence as faithful and serviceable a representation of the conditions under which phenomena appear as may be possible.

Formerly science pretended to be the absolute knowledge of the nature of things, knowledge which is certain and definitive, as opposed to belief which is variable and individual; but this concept of science as absolute and illimitable has not been maintained. At the moment, science holds that it is based on experience and on experience only.

Thus, by giving to man the means whereby he may induce nature to repeat herself, it lays hold on reality. It escapes from the everlasting and infinite variety of opinion. In this sense, it is to only compelling on all intelligences, but all its acquisitions are definitive. But, on the other hand, these very assets form a limitation of its extent and its philosophic value.

Boutroux defined the scientific spirit as essentially “The fact considered as the source, the rule, the measure and the control of all knowledge”.

The Fact.

But a fact, from the standpoint of science, is not merely a reality which may be ascertained or verified. The investigator who proposes to establish a fact, sets himself before this fact and observes it, as could any other individual, equally motivated solely by a desire for knowledge. In this sense, he applies himself to discern, to watch, to reckon, to express by means of symbols and, if possible, to measure this phenomenon. But the reflecting mind wonders whether experience can furnish nothing more than mere fact, and whether it would not be possible, solely under the guidance of this same experience, to pass beyond the fact as here defined and attain to that which we call law.

The real object of science is essentially to explain the fact through the discovery of the laws which govern it.

In beginning this study, in order to avoid the sophisms, the false ideas and ambiguities which cling to words, it is necessary to rigorously define the terms employed.

Law.

Law (Latin, lex) is defined as the necessary linkage by which phenomena succeed one another, or more simply:.

“A constant relationship, invariable and necessary,.

uniting two phenomena.”4 (4. Larousse. Encyclopaedia).

Regnault (5) (Regnault. Precis de logique evolutionniste. Bib. phil., p. 118.) defines it: “The regular sequel (or the idea therein) indefinitely identical, of effects of the same cause.” According to Boutroux6 [Boutroux. Loc. cit.] is is the coupling of phenomena. to Montesquieu, it is the necessary relationship existing in the nature of things.

In order to be of a scientific character, law must be based on observation and on experience; moreover, it must analyse the circumstances producing phenomena and resynthesize them with respect to their normal relationships of similarity and succession. Littre. Dictionary of Medicine. Art. : Law.

This idea of law is the directing concept of modern science. Unquestionably, it is every old; even in the days of Greek science, investigators such as Archimedes found laws analogous to those which our physicists formulate. But it is only in our day that it has become the fundamental idea of science.

Thus, the law of falling bodies is a constant relationship; invariable and necessary: during a given time, a falling body always traverses the same distance.

Of course, such accuracy in the determination of law cannot be the object of all sciences. When biology, for instance, investigates the behaviour of an organism under variations of its environment, it does not pretend to measure these variations. It is, however, no less true that all sciences work toward the establishment of a definite law.

Science, thus, by general recognition, is characterised by its endeavor to discover the constant, invariable and necessary relationships existing between the facts of observation.

Medicine.

Despite the present tendency to consider applied medicine as a science, it possesses neither principle nor law in anything resembling therapeutic medication.

In general definition, medicine is at one time both an art and a science; a science in its scientific perception, an art in its application. But there are times when all recognition of a scientific character is denied. In the last edition of the dictionary of medicine, Littre defines it as follows:.

“An art and not a science, for it seeks a practical result and not a scientific truth. It rests on individual procedures and not on principles or constant formulations”.

This definition, however, cannot be considered as adequate today. In reality, while surgery, anatomy and physiology are rapidly becoming medical sciences, therapy remains as ever an art, pure and simple, inasmuch as no law has been formulated in accordance with which the physician decrees his prescription.

Anyone is capable of understanding the science of medicine, and most succeed in brilliantly passing their examinations. In spite of this, however, many are incapable of applying and practicing that which one may still call the medical art, the art of healing. To apprehend the mere science, application and perseverance coupled with intelligence are necessary. The art requires more.

If the physician has not the love of his art and his profession, united with a sincere desire to heal, he cannot succeed. But though he may combine all these qualities, lacking a law and principle of therapy, he lacks a compass, he wanders aimlessly, dependent on authority, obliged to follow hidden paths, to pay homage to the goddess called “Fashion,” who exists unfortunately even in medicine.

Therapeutic treatises of past centuries hold for us today nothing more than historic interest and amusement, for the interpretations and the hypotheses built on the experiences of that period have been modified by a succeeding age. And to the extent to which theories change, therapeutic agents change also.

At first it seemed as though theories lasted only a few moments, and that ruins were piled on ruins. On one day they are born, on the following they are the mode, the third day they are classic, and the fourth they are obsolete. But if one searches more profoundly, one sees that those which die in this fashion are theories, properly so-called theories which pretend to teach us the nature of things.

However, they frequently hold within themselves a something which survives. If one of them has shown us a true relationship, the knowledge of that relationship is definitely acquired and one finds it again, disguised anew in the other theories which have successively reigned in its place. This certainly should give us a little courage!.

Today, the traveller is struck by the realization of the extent to which the great medical centres of different countries lack unity of opinion concerning the administration, as well as the choice and the dosage of remedies. Here it is opotherapy, there vaccino-therapy, somewhere else serotherapy, which is being developed and tested. Still elsewhere a scepticism born of past experiences and an examination of statistics brings a return to the Hippocratean method of expectation, or reinstates physiotherapy as the only method of treatment, “primum non nocere” becoming the order of the day.

Pierre Schmidt
Pierre Schmidt M.D.(1894-1987)
Dr. Schmidt was introduced to the results of homeopathic treatment during the 1918 flu epidemic while living in London. There he met both J. H. Clarke and John Weir.
In 1922 he came to the United States and began his studies with Alonzo Austin and Frederica Gladwin, who had been a pupil of Kent's. He became the first graduate of the American Foundation for Homeopathy course for doctors. Returning to his native land he set up practice in Geneva, Switzerland. He was responsible for reintroducing classical homeopathy into Europe, teaching several generations of physicians, including Elizabeth Wright Hubbard.
Dr. Schmidt helped edit the "Final General Repertory" of Kent, and translated the Organon into French. In 1925, he was one of the main founders of the Liga Medicorum Homoeopathic Internationalis (LIGA).